Skeptoid PodcastSkeptoid on Facebook   Skeptoid on Twitter   Skeptoid on Spotify   iTunes   Google Play

Members Portal

Support Us Store

 

Free Book

 

Asking the Socratic Questions

Donate A line of reasoning named for Socrates helps us help believers in the strange re-examine their beliefs.  

by Brian Dunning

Filed under Logic & Persuasion

Skeptoid Podcast #384
October 15, 2013
Podcast transcript | Subscribe

Listen on Apple Podcasts Listen on Spotify

Share Tweet Reddit

Asking the Socratic Questions

Of all the possible perspectives, beliefs, theories, ideologies, and conclusions in this world, which of them are beyond question? None of them. And neither should be any person who holds one of those positions. People believe all sorts of strange things, and even though they might be passionate about them, most will still admit that questioning their belief is an appropriate undertaking. Therefore, we — as scientific skeptics — have an available avenue by which we can always encourage believers in the strange to revisit their beliefs. Despite the fact that we may lack professional expertise in the subject at hand, we can still plant the seeds of an uprising of logic within the mind of the believer. One way to do this is through the application of Socratic questioning.

Returning to our fake example guys used in the past, Starling and Bombo, we can illustrate this concept. Let us choose an example scenario. If Bombo has seen a UFO and believes that it was an alien spacecraft, it would likely be difficult for Starling to reason him out of the idea by offering alternative suggestions. People are often pretty stubborn when it comes to personal experiences that they've already interpreted for themselves; Bombo saw an alien spacecraft, and telling him it was the planet Venus would probably be a dead end. Indeed, even offering lines of logic for Bombo to follow on his own would probably be refused. So is there any effective way at all of getting someone to consider a different explanation?

The answer is yes, and it involves getting Bombo to arrive at alternate explanations on his own. We're all far more prone to accept our own ideas than someone else's. Starling might well able to get Bombo to consider the idea that the UFO might not have been an alien spacecraft by employing Socratic questioning. Named (quite obviously) for Socrates — the ancient Greek philosopher (also quite obviously) — the Socratic questions are primarily teaching tools. Just as Bombo better accepts his own ideas, so do students of all types. Socratic questioning helps people to take a second, closer look at their own beliefs, and to apply critical thinking even when they least expect it.

There are six commonly described categories of Socratic questions, and they're all good. You could familiarize yourself with any one of them, and you'd have a pretty good chance at changing Bombo's mind, or that of anyone else who has made a conclusion based on faulty logic. An adept at all six types of questions would be a formidable reformer of popular pseudoscience believers.

Let's begin with the first type:

1. Questions of Clarification

In order to engage Bombo's critical analysis of his own conclusion, we must first make certain that Bombo's conclusion is clear in his own mind. For example:

Bombo: "I saw a UFO, and it was an alien spacecraft."

A great way to start is to make darn sure that Bombo understands the full force of what he's saying, which (assuming his belief is invalid) almost always raises a fatal weakness. Let's see if we can get him to clarify exactly what he's arguing:

Starling: "Just so I'm clear, do you mean you saw something unidentified, or you actually identified it as something from another planet?"

That one question might be all it takes. Bombo might reflect for a moment, and then realize that all he can really say is that he saw something that he couldn't identify. Discussion over; Starling 1, Bombo 0; rationality 1, UFOlogy 0. However such an easy and early victory would not make this into much of an episode, so throughout, we're going to proceed as if nothing sways Bombo.

Let us continue to clarify, and keep the focus on the invalid part of Bombo's claim.

Starling: "What exactly do you mean by alien?"

Keep the crosshairs on the target. If Bombo is going to promote his claim, we want to make sure his only way out is to promote it very specifically and in no uncertain terms. Socratic questions of clarification are a great way to do this. You can even ask something like this:

Starling: "Are you saying you found sufficient reason to conclude that what you witnessed was an actual manned spacecraft from another planet?"

Of course, in reality, Bombo is likely to blurt out at any time:

Bombo: "What's with all these stupid questions? Do you think I'm lying, or what?"

He might reasonably say that now, or at any time during the rest of these categories, and it's a perfectly natural response. But if or when he ever does say this, you've got a perfectly rational answer that even Bombo can't disagree with:

Starling: "Wouldn't you agree these are important questions?"

Bombo's the one making the outlandish claim; he's always going to agree that questions clarifying his claim are important. We can now move on to the assumptions Bombo has made that have allowed him to make his conclusion.

2. Questions that Probe Assumptions

Remember it's not all about Bombo's specific claim; it's about the faulty assumptions he has made about the world that give his claim a disguise of plausibility. So force Bombo to admit exactly what those assumptions are:

Starling: "Sounds like you're assuming that aliens visit the Earth. Is that correct?"

That's one facet of his claim. It has others, so let's look at those as well. One thing that characterizes many false claims is the existence of something that actually doesn't exist, like life force, ghosts, or other things that the claim depends on. Here we can force Bombo to re-examine his ability to have identified an alien spacecraft:

Starling: "What are the characteristics of alien spacecraft?"

Of course he doesn't know, and of course he agrees it's an important question. So it's always interesting to see where he'll go from here. But, in my experience, sally forth he will. Push him harder.

Starling: "Should we take those assumptions as fact; or should we leave them open?"

Remember, when you're putting Bombo in a corner, any direction you push him is going to put him further into the corner (insisting his assumptions be immune to question) or you're successfully getting him to back down (admitting his assumptions should be considered open questions). Next let's see how he got to the conclusion he did.

3. Questions that Probe Reasons and Evidence

Get Bombo to take another look at the quality of his evidence and the reasons he found it convincing.

Starling: "How were you able to make a positive identification of 'alien'?"

Of course there's no way he logically could have; but manage to, he did. If he's going to make a specific claim, then he must have some reasoning or evidence behind it that led him there. That reasoning must have allowed him to make this distinction:

Starling: "How would some secret new Earthly aircraft have behaved or appeared differently?"

Again, he's not going to know, so he either has to paint himself further into his corner, or he has to back off and admit the weakness of his position. Either way, the Socratic questions are making progress.

Since the claim Bombo is making is a factual one, it's therefore testable. Most likely Bombo has not done any actual testing that led to his conclusion, and neither has anyone else; but every factual claim must be able to pass this question:

Starling: "How would you verify or disprove that the UFO was an alien spacecraft?"

Next let's see if we can get him to question his preconceived notions.

4. Questions about Viewpoints or Perspectives

Is Bombo's fundamental viewpoint logically invalid?

Starling: "You seem to have the perspective that anything unfamiliar to your personal experience must be alien. Is that correct?"

This is not a straw man argument. What Bombo saw was unfamiliar, and he refused to allow the possibility that there might be Earthly things in the sky that he didn't recognize. He did not conclude:

Bombo: "It's either an alien spacecraft, or it's something I don't recognize."

He said:

Bombo: "It's an alien spacecraft."

So it's a fair question. It's also fair to see if he might be simply repeating pop tripe:

Starling: "Have you ever seen anything in the media that might have influenced your identification?"

Or here's a good one. Get Bombo to honestly acknowledge what people from a different perspective would conclude about his observation:

Starling: "How do you think people who don't believe in aliens might have identified what you saw, if they'd seen it too?"

5. Questions that Probe Implications and Consequences

Pseudoscientific claims often imply facts that, if they were true, would have tremendous impacts on our world. Think what a cure for cancer would do if it existed, or the implications if the government were found to have faked the moon landing. Encourage Bombo to see that his claim would have similar consequences; consequences that have so far failed to materialize:

Starling: "What do you think the consequences of this will be?"

Or:

Starling: "How would this change our knowledge of the universe?"

Obviously, it would overturn much of what we think we know. Don't you think someone in science or government would have expressed an interest if so much of astrophysics were suddenly proven wrong?

Or even the practical implications for the day-to-day guy on the street:

Starling: "Do you think the news or the military should do anything about it?"

If Bombo's claim were true, the whole world would be in a huge fit. It's not; so what does Bombo have to conclude?

6. Questions about the Question

At any time, as mentioned previously, Bombo is likely to attack the questions themselves. Skeptical inquiry is, of course, the greatest enemy of falsehood. If that happens, ask something like this:

Starling: "Why do you think I'm asking these questions?"

Or:

Starling: "Are these questions making sense to you?"

And finally, the most important question, that you probably will have already had to ask by now:

Starling: "Do you think these are important questions that should be asked?"

...and it really is the most important question. Nobody in the world wants to admit that their position is so tenuous that it can't withstand any questions, and so when put on the spot, they'll almost always agree that the questions which might lead to their position being found true should be asked. Once in a while you'll get:

Bombo: "No, my position is right, there's no point in questioning it."

...but even though he might say those words, he'll feel disingenuous even as they're coming out of his mouth. And he will reflect to himself, either now or later, that his assumptions and perspectives should be questioned. Because they should. Always. For everyone. On every subject. If your facts are right, you'll breeze through such questions. Everyone should welcome them, no matter what your perspective or your claim.

In fact, I'll go out on a limb. If anyone feels that Socratic questioning is unfair to their particular field, one that the mainstream considers to be pseudoscience, email me. I'll be happy to do a specific episode addressing this, and I'll be happy to include your comments.


By Brian Dunning

Please contact us with any corrections or feedback.

 

Shop apparel, books, & closeouts

Share Tweet Reddit

Cite this article:
Dunning, B. "Asking the Socratic Questions." Skeptoid Podcast. Skeptoid Media, 15 Oct 2013. Web. 18 Mar 2024. <https://skeptoid.com/episodes/4384>

 

References & Further Reading

Fadiman, C. Socrates and the Slave. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1958.

Fogler, H., Gürmen, M. "The Six Types of Socratic Questions." Strategies for Creative Problem Solving. University of Michigan, 13 Sep. 2013. Web. 10 Oct. 2013. <http://www.umich.edu/~elements/probsolv/strategy/cthinking.htm>

Gower, B., Stokes, M. Socratic Questions: New Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates and Its Significance. London: Routledge, 1992.

Hintikka, J. Socratic Epistemology: Explorations of Knowledge-Seeking by Questioning. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

Kirkland, S. The Ontology of Socratic Questioning in Plato's Early Dialogues. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2012.

Wilcomb, R., Wilcox, M. "Socratic Questioning." Physics Teacher Education Program. Illinois State University, 4 Oct. 2012. Web. 11 Oct. 2013. <http://www.phy.ilstu.edu/pte/310content/case_studies/resources/socratic_questioning.pdf>

 

©2024 Skeptoid Media, Inc. All Rights Reserved. Rights and reuse information

 

 

 

Donate

 

 


Shop: Apparel, books, closeouts

 

 

Now Trending...

How to Extract Adrenochrome from Children

Tartaria and the Mud Flood

The Myers-Briggs Personality Test

Exploring Kincaid's Cave

The Historicity of Jesus Christ

St. Patrick's Day Myths

The Red Haired Giants of Lovelock Cave

The Siberian Hell Sounds

 

Want more great stuff like this?

Let us email you a link to each week's new episode. Cancel at any time: